1. Reflections on the Holland Conference[1]
On March 28-30, 1974, Equitarian Associates, in
conjunction with the Midwest Society for Philosophic Investigations, held what may have been the most important intellectual
conference of the year. The topic of the conference was “Libertarianism and Justice,” and it took place at Point
West in Macatawa, Michigan, just outside Holland. Speakers included Dr. John Hospers (head of the school of philosophy at
USC), Douglas Rasmussen (Ph.D. candidate in philosophy at Marquette University in Milwaukee, Wisconsin), Joel Myklebust (a
bio-medical engineer from Marquette), Dr. Eric Mack (professor of philosophy at Eisenhower College), Roger Bissell (professional
musician and author in the special Ayn Rand issue of Reason magazine), Bruce Den Uyl (honors student in economics
and geology at Lawrence University), Dr. Tibor Machan (professor of philosophy at SUNY at Fredonia and editor of Reason
magazine), and Douglas Den Uyl (graduate student in political philosophy at the University of Chicago and author in the special
Ayn Rand issue of Reason magazine). Paper topics ranged from “Justice and Punishment” to “The Theory
of Economic Externalities and Justice.” Following is the text of my April 1974 editorial.
Sunday,
March 31, 1974/Somewhere south of Indianapolis—Speeding
down I-65 in my cute, economical, little red Toyota wagon, I am putting down these notes on the Holland, Michigan Equitarian
Conference (Mar. 28-30) while they are still fresh in my mind. Keeping one eye on my notepad and pen, and one eye out for
the Indiana Highway Patrol I say to myself, “Self, to hell with our Energy Chief’s national speed limit—the
time I save is worth more to me (and to the country) than the extra gas I use.” All the while, I keep the fingers of
my steering wheel hand crossed in blind hope that there will be a gas station operator up ahead in Louisville, whose March
gasoline allocation has not yet run dry. As if to italicize my state of mind, two lumber trucks pass me at 65+ miles per hour,
with bumper stickers saying, “More Speed! And Fuel!”
Which seems an apt
transitional idea into my comments on the conference. It went fast (especially for me, since I missed the first two days),
but it gave considerable fuel to our hopes for working out the outstanding problems for Libertarian and Equitarian political
and legal theory.
The government controversy:
I got the first real indication that anarchist Libertarians are beginning to grasp and accept the expanded concept of “government,”
which Tibor Machan and I have been advocating. The more limited, naïve interpretation of the various concepts in Ayn
Rand’s statements on government, made by many limited governmentalists and anarchists alike, has prolonged the archy-anarchy
debate for far too long.
The legal justice controversy:
For the first time in history, several of the most influential theorists and spokesmen for the Libertarian movement were assembled
together in a forum where they could bare and thrash out their differences on the issues of punishment and restitution. Most
people were able to come away with a firm distinction between restitution and self-defense on the one hand, and punishment
on the other, no longer including the former with the latter under the broad label of “punishment.”
No
one could give a definitive argument that a criminal loses or suspends his rights when he commits a crime, and can thus be
punished without violating his rights, though Tibor Machan and I both indicated the only plausible direction such
an argument could take. (Credit goes to Douglas Rasmussen for suggesting it to me several days before the conference.) If
the criminal does not negate (remove from himself) his humanness, then the only other necessary condition underlying
his rights which he could somehow negate (remove from himself) is the social context within which the principle of
rights arises.
The argument was sketched out like this: ethical egoism’s concept of justice includes the obligation to
treat persons so as to exclude them from society, if they have themselves demonstrated by their actions that they have
broken the logically necessary precondition for their entering into social relationships with us (and we with them), and that
they do in fact demonstrate this if they intentionally violate another’s rights. The major problem with this is that
it does not go far enough to establish a valid basis for punishment, as opposed to mere voluntary refusal, on a one-to-one
basis, to associate with the guilty party.
What is needed in addition is a proof that it is
morally obligatory for us to set up a system which allows a small number of man to decide whether or not all
men must agree to the forcible exclusion of the criminal from society—i.e., whether we ought to delegate
our right of ostracism to our protective agency or government. (By “right to ostracize,” I mean the right to voluntarily
refuse to deal with someone, which is merely a corollary of the right to free association.) While Tibor Machan and Douglas
Rasmussen go to work on this problem, Milo Schield [co-founder of Equitarian Associates], Joel Myklebust, Eric Mack, I and
others will prepare our logical fine-tooth combs to detect any flaws in their arguments—and if none exist, then I guess
Equitarianism will become a theory of self-defense, restitution, and punishment. Not until then, though.
On
the balance sheet, the status of restitution and self-defense vs. punishment was pretty much as follows:
Ø On the one hand, it was generally conceded that
punishment was not sufficient for justice (restitution and self-defense being necessary, either also, or instead);
and furthermore, it was not agreed that punishment was necessary either. On the other hand, it was
conceded that restitution and self-defense were necessary (whenever possible) for justice, but it was not agreed
that they were sufficient. Punishment advocates say since restitution is not always possible (and, they say, it is
necessary that something be done to the criminal to serve justice), something more than restitution and self-defense
is necessary. (Some say that the discrepancy between the treatment of a crime-of-passion murder with heavy restitution and
a coldly-plotted murder with little or no restitution—clearly a possibility—is a fatal argument against the restitution/self-defense
theory. Others add that ostracism would probably be ineffective against the worst criminals, who would e welcomed with open
arms by criminal organizations.) Restitution advocates challenge this premise that “something” be done to the
criminal in the legal sphere (beyond restitution and self-defense). They say the moral-social sphere of voluntary
association is adequate for handling the moral discrepancies between the crime-of-passion and coldly-plotted (as
well as negligence-caused) crimes; the legal discrepancies reside solely in the rights claims which must be rectified
by restitution. (The principle here lies in the moral-legal distinction, where morality deals with intent, whereas the law
is concerned not with intent so much as with responsibility.) Furthermore, if so much time and money were not spent in other
areas by government (including imprisonment), the legal agencies could much more effectively deal with and limit the influence
of criminal organizations, so that the criminal would much more likely have nowhere very promising to turn within
society.
Ø
Restitution advocates
pointed out that theirs was a theory not of strict responsibility, but restoration modified by the criminal’s degree
of responsibility for the results of his crime, and the cost of his apprehension, detention, and trial. Still problems remain
in (a) measuring full restoration value (“market value” vs. what the victim can prove the lost value
was worth to him on his value-hierarchy), and (b) determining the nature of legal responsibility (strict liability
for all effects of one’s actions, vs. liability only for consequences of acts which the most knowledgeable man could
have foreseen and avoided, vs. liability only for consequences of acts which the given rights-violator could have foreseen
and avoided). It was conceded that restitution in terms of value-equivalents was legitimate, but many would not agree that
forcing the criminal to make restitution did not violate his rights (given the restitution theory premise that criminals retain
their rights), until it was pointed out that the only minimum necessary force is permitted, and that his rights do not include
the right to act so as to prevent you from recovering the values which he has taken away. Punishment advocates had a major
problem themselves in justifying the form and amount of punishment, though Tibor Machan suggested an interesting possibility:
a “time of life” criterion to be applied in determining the length of imprisonment (though it needs to be worked
out along with the justification of imprisonment itself).
Clearly, no manifesto
will issue forth from this conference. Yet, it is equally clearly a crucial landmark in the development of a Libertarian theory
of legal justice. The outstanding problems with the restitution and punishment theories were discussed and clarified as never
before. Despite the considerable emotional resistance involved in such issues as punishment, intent, legal responsibility,
etc., the area of legal justice is yielding slowly but surely to the light of reason. I am not alone in feeling more confident
than ever that those problems will be conclusively resolved, and quite possibly within the next two years or so.
The
tremendous benefit of such a resolution, whichever way it goes (pro- or anti-punishment), lies in the fact that we will necessarily
achieve a much more thorough grasp of the concepts of “men’s rights” and “justice.” Perhaps
this, rather than the oft-quoted goal of “freedom in our time,” is a legacy which we can realistically
hope to pass on to future generations.
Reason without freedom is frustrating as hell,
but freedom without a fully justified rational basis for it is even worse, for you are then heading down the road to statism
(as America has since 1776), instead of up toward a free society (as we may yet be, if it is not too late). I do not mean
to argue against activism, even against the Libertarian Party, merely to point out that the longest-range importance
lies in getting the firmest possible basis for freedom spread as rapidly through our culture as possible.
And
if this most recent Equitarian conference is any indication, I think we Libertarians may be able to finish the work Thomas
Jefferson outlined in The Declaration of Independence, in time for its 200th anniversary. Perhaps a fitting
name for the document would be: The Declaration of Justice.
2. On
the Matter of the Punishment of Criminals[2]
An Open Letter to the Libertarian Party Platform
Committee
The aim of
this Open Letter is twofold: (1) to argue against what seems to be a widespread Libertarian tendency to regard the punishment
of criminals as a just way of dealing with them; and (2) to suggest that there are moral options open to us in this
area which would not have the effect of turning society as we know it into more of a jungle than it already is. I
direct my comments to you Committee members so that you may consider adding a plank in repudiation of punishment in our party
platform.
The Argument Against Punishment:
The punishment of criminals is immoral and unjust, tragically so, since certain perfectly legitimate methods are quite sufficient
(even superior) alternatives to punishment—methods which are often incorporated into punishment, but even then vastly
underemphasized.
The basis of my argument is man’s rights. On the one hand, the criminal does not and cannot lose his
rights merely be committing a crime per se, and thus cannot justifiably be imprisoned, for instance, merely because
he has committed a crime and thus (supposedly) “deserves” imprisonment qua imprisonment.
On
the other hand, the victim (and perhaps potential victims) has the right to self-defense and restitution against the criminal,
and thus, again for instance, imprisonment may be the minimum force necessary to protect those rights—not,
I must emphasize, imprisonment qua imprisonment, but instead, imprisonment qua protection of rights.
As
I understand them, these principles constitute the backbone of the identifications made in the field of criminal law by the
Equitarian Associates over the past four years. They are a sorely needed addition to the growing body of Libertarian theory
based upon the Axiom of Non-Aggression (i.e., the principle of Man’s Rights). They are a welcome contrast to the badly
confused views held, I fear, by many Libertarians.
The main fact I find
to support this claim is that after Professor John Hospers’ two-part article on force and punishment appear in Reason
a year ago, not one letter was printed in protest. [I sent a letter making points substantially similar to those in this essay,
but it, along with Professor Hospers’ reply, was rejected for publication.] For the remainder of this Open Letter, then,
I will focus my criticism on that article by Professor Hospers, in order to more fully illuminate, by contrast, the Equitarian
(and proper Libertarian) position.
“Deserts” Vs. “Results”:
A False Alternative: The article in question
is “Some Problems about Punishment and the Retaliatory Use of Force,” which appeared in the November 1972 and
January 1973 issues of Reason. In particular, I take serious objection to the section in part 2 entitled “How
Much Retaliation Should Be Used?” in which Professor Hospers discusses the basic theories of punishment.
Hospers
begins by saying that the proper retaliation for a crime depends largely on “one’s theory of the function of punishment.”
(Reason, January1973, p. 20) He contrasts the retributive and utilitarian (or “deserts”
and “results”) theories, maintaining that the former is on better grounds.
A
person should be punished as retribution for his crime, “because he has committed a crime and should not be
punished if he has not committed it, no matter how much good by way of deterrence, etc., punishing him may do.” (Ibid.,
p. 21) In other words, to justify punishing a person, we do so by reference not to desired future results, but to the past
criminal offense.
This raises some serious problems. First of all, retaliation is the act of forcibly restraining a wrongdoer’s
freedom of action with regard to his person, property, or liberty, in response to his misdeed. Quite obviously, this involves
the area of the criminal’s rights, which would seem to place a limit on not jus the amount, but the kind
of retaliation taken against him. Now, it is not at all clear to me just how the criminal deserves and should have
punitive retaliation—i.e., punishment, the category of retaliation where one does so for the primary purpose
of making the wrongdoer suffer for his misdeed (whether to reform him, deter others, or make him suffer per se)—“just
because” he has committed a crime.
This seems to be a categorical imperative,
instead of the conditional type of imperative tied to consequences or results, with which I feel much more comfortable
in moral and legal discussions. In other words, Professor Hospers merely claims that criminal guilt (rather than
the hope for reform, deterrence, etc.) is a sufficient condition for punishment—he has offered no objectively justifiable
purpose for punishment.
Non-Punitive Retaliation:
Now, since Professor Hospers has already adequately disposed of various “results” justifications of punishment,
and since we have no likely new candidates, it would be well to consider whether there are any non-punitive forms
of retaliation which are logically supportable.
There are, in fact, two: defense and restitution.
These two forms of retaliation are logically derivable from the victim’s rights, and are held as claims against anyone
who unjustly attacks and harms him.
Thus, there is justification both with reference
to the past and to the future: in the case of defense, to the past initiation (or threat) of force, and
the future prevention of successful completion of that initiation—in the case of restitution, to the past initiation
of force resulting in loss of values, and to the future prevention of the criminal’s keeping those values away from
one.
Furthermore, there is justification both with respect to deserts and results. An aggressor and
only an aggressor deserves defensive and restitutive retaliation, since it is an aggressor and no one else who is
trying to take away the values which you rightfully deserve to keep. And properly limited defensive and restitutive retaliation
results (hopefully) in one’s keeping or recovering one’s rightfully possessed values.
In
other words, restitution and defense are retaliatory actions directed against a rights violator for the purpose of protecting
the victim’s rights. This very function Ayn Rand properly attributes to government in her essay “The Nature of
Government” in The Virtue of Selfishness, though she, Professor Hospers, and many if not most Libertarians
go beyond this seemingly clear-cut limitation on the retaliatory force permissible to government.
Several
Neglected Distinctions: At this point, let us
note that Professor Hospers’ including punishment as a legitimate activity of government is only partly based upon the
false alternative view I have criticized above. It is also rooted in his failure to make several important distinctions in
his article. Perhaps a clear identification of them can melt away the remaining aversion any of you Committee members may
feel toward the anti-punishment view.
First, Professor Hospers includes retaliation
for the protection of others (e.g., imprisonment) as punishment. At least, from his article, one gets no indication that
he would not do so. At most, I suspect he would probably describe it as punishment with a misguided justification,
or something to that effect: “I would hope that punishment in a particular case would do as much good as possible, by
way of deterrence, reformation, and protection; but that is not the reason why a person should be punished…”
(Ibid., p. 21)
But, in fact, such retaliation is not punishment at all. Its primary purpose is not to punish the criminal,
but to restrain him from violating others’ rights by his aggression.
Secondly,
and more explicitly, Professor Hospers includes retaliation for the purpose of restitution as punishment. “I
do not deny that restitution to the injured party should, when possible, constitute a part of the aggressor’s punishment…”
(Ibid., p. 22)
Again, however, restitution is not punishment-directed at all. Instead, its primary purpose is o force the
criminal to undo the economic impact of his crime upon the victim. Naturally, this may involve the holding of the criminal
so that he cannot avoid making restitution by fleeing the country.
A third and quite
distressing confusion is the lumping together of opponents of punishment with pacifists:
Some libertarians, insistent on the non-initiation of force to the point of pacifism, apparently believe that no
punishment whatever is justified for any offense under any circumstances. Part of the reason for this is the belief that no
one has the right to do violence to another, even in retaliation. (Ibid., p. 22)
This
passage contains a serious error: it confuses opposition to punishment and retaliatory force with pacifism. But since
pacifists reject all force (initiatory and retaliatory), this omits the possibility of a position rejecting only
initiatory and punitively retaliatory force, yet accepting restitutive and defensive retaliatory force.
This
omission leads Professor Hospers to say that the opposition to punishment “would encourage crime and permit psychotic
killers to be loose on the streets.” (Ibid., p. 22) Now, whether defensive and restitutive retaliatory force minus punishment
would encourage crime is at best doubtful. But only in a three-fourths statist society such as ours can one reasonably worry
about what streets psychotic killers would be permitted to be loose on. As Professor Rothbard and others have pointed
out, this problem would be taken care of quite nicely by fully private ownership of streets and roads.
Professor
Hospers continues immediately with the following non sequitur: “Example: when the Montreal police force went on strike
recently, crimes of most kinds quadrupled within a few days.” (Ibid., p. 22) But surely this is not a clear-cut example
of the consequences of no punishment. Might it not instead be an example of the consequences of no defensive
and restitutive retaliatory force? Here we seem to have an example of the first two unmade distinctions combined. At
any rate, it weighs heavily on Professor Hospers to show how, with a police force to apprehend and thwart criminals,
the absence of punishment would cause a rise in crime.
In the last sentence
of that paragraph, Professor Hospers says: “No society can long survive without some provision for punishment.”
(Ibid., p. 22) By now, we can clearly see the correction which needs to be made to this statement: No society can long
survive without some provision for defensive and restitutive retaliatory force.
Further Challenges to the Non-Punishment Position: Another challenge to the restitutive theory occurs in the next
paragraph where Professor Hospers claims that substituting restitution for punishment “would wipe out at one stroke
the legal distinctions carefully built up between murder and manslaughter, and the further distinctions of degree between
each of these categories.” (Ibid., p. 22)
My reply to this is that only the legal
distinctions would be eliminated, not the moral ones. We still have the powerful weapon of our voluntary refusal
to deal with vicious criminals, of ostracism, and in the case of negligent individuals, to be less trustful of them
in the future.
As indicated earlier, a fully implemented system of private ownership of roads and streets would greatly enhance
the efforts of the police force in protecting the rights of decent, law-abiding individuals. Let those who choose to deal
with a criminal to do so at their own expense and risk (including the risk of our censure). After all, in a free society,
one’s reputation is one’s foremost social asset—or liability.
I
want it to be clearly understood that ostracism is not all that I recommend in dealing with criminals. Indeed, imprisonment
may well be necessary, not as punishment, but as self-defense (assuming that the guilty person is a threat to one’s
own rights) or as the means of restitution.
Professor Hospers
himself stressed the defensive aspect of imprisonment in an unpublished letter to Reason last year, in which he pointed
out the unpleasant prospect of a (successful or unsuccessful) murderer going scot-free. I feel no qualms about agreeing with
him on this point, nor when he says in his letter, in regard to the axe-murderer: “…I wouldn’t feel very
safe in a society in which the only thing done to a killer was to ignore him.” (my emphasis)
Beyond
this confusion of defensive imprisonment with punishment, and the justification of the former with the lack of justification
of the latter, Professor Hospers does not offer support for his insistence upon the necessity of what he calls “punishment”
for guilty persons.
Conclusion: It is far from clear why justice would not be fully served by
strictly limiting the legal use of force to defense and restitution of values, and limiting reprisals to purely non-coercive,
social sanctions against the criminal. The onus of proof must surely lie upon those Libertarians and others who claim that
justice requires more than this.
In
light of the recent calls for re-institution of the death penalty by President Nixon and others, it is an especially opportune
moment in history for Libertarians to take a firm stand against punishment, an unnecessary evil.
3. None Dare Call It Non-Punishment[iii]
The Semantics of Retaliation
It seems that, as in the archy-anarchy dispute, the established modes
of thought and speech militate against our calling a spade a spade. For some time, I have anguished over the question as to
why anarcho-capitalists persist in claiming that the associations established around free-market police and arbitration agencies
are not governments, when, in plain fact, they are. Similarly, I fretfully ask: why must retributivists persist in
claiming that self-defense is punishment, when, in plain fact, it is not?
Merely
because the overt harmful physical result of imprisoning a man as punishment for a crime may be the same as that
of imprisoning him because the nature of his crime and his execution of it establish the need to do so as self-defense?
There seems good reason not to equate the terms in such a manner.
First
of all, punishment includes things not included as self-defense—e.g., punishment of “victimless crime” lawbreakers.
And self-defense includes things not included as punishment—e.g., locking one’s doors and windows at night, installing
an alarm system, etc.
More fundamentally, however, even in the area where the two concepts appear to overlap, they are sharply distinguished
by the purpose which the retaliatory action is intended to serve.
Ø Punishment is for the purpose of changing the criminal’s
psychological state—to make him suffer (retribution, or perhaps vengeance), to discourage him from repeating his act
(deterrence), to direct his conscience to proper social behavior (rehabilitation), or whatever.
Ø Self-defense is for the purpose of protecting oneself
and others against criminals. Both or neither punishment or self-defense may entail, for instance, imprisonment—society-wide
ostracism—but if they do, they are still performing different functions.
To
call any forcible harm done to a criminal “punishment” is to fail to focus on the basic purpose of what
was done—just as to call any forcible reprisal “retaliatory force” is to fail to focus on the amount of
force used relative to the minimum amount necessary to protect or regain one’s values (the former amount constituting
initiatory force, if it is excessive).
What is the basic purpose of one’s
actions toward a criminal? Is it to change the criminal’s psychological state, for whatever further end—or to
protect oneself, by whatever effective means? That, punishment advocates, is the difference between punishment and self-defense,
in those cases where they appear to be one and the same.
4. Another
View of Punishment[iv]
Lee’s Ethical Egoist Theory of Punishment
There are many theories and notions of punishment floating around these
days—few of the Libertarian in name, even fewer being proven or plausible. A healthy exception to this would seem to
be that presented by J. Roger Lee, “Reflections on Punishment,” in The Libertarian Alternative (ed. Tibor
R. Machan, pub. Chicago: Nelson-Hall Co., 1974, pp. 56-66). In this essay, Lee proposes to construct a theory of punishment
consistent with ethical egoism.
Lee shows conclusively that both the utilitarian
and the retributive theories are inadequate for satisfying the conditions of egoism. In particular, retributivists fail to
prove to use why we ought to punish a “deserving” individual, whether in the sense of “desert”
where “the punishment was appropriate to the wrong act” (pp. 58-9), or the sense where “a person gets all
the causal consequences of his action” (pp. 59-60).
Let also rejects the
“seductively simple proposition—that there is no need for punishment, that if we who do right actions merely leave
the perpetrators of wrong actions alone, then reality will insure that the wrongdoers fail while we who do the right will
prosper” (p. 62). This view is faulty because (1) men are valuable to each other only in productive, trader relations,
(2) individuals can find value in associating with each other only on the basis of free exchange of goods and services, and
(3) each man’s interest entails the provision that such exchanges of values are the only such exchanges allowed in the
society, that only rational exchange, not force or fraud, is permitted (p. 62). Punishment, Lee believes, acts against these
three weaknesses of a society without punishment and “will thus maximize the good for each individual that
can be found in the society in which he lives” (p. 62).
Punishment is necessary
in addition to defense, Lee maintains, because “defense…is anticipatory,” and the response to a wrong action
after it has been taken is “something other than defense…[namely] retribution [i.e., restitution], and
than punishment” (p. 63). In general, punishment is supposed to keep society safe for “peaceful exchange among
reasonable men,” by (1) making the cost of non-peaceful exchange discouragingly high, and (2) implementing the expression
of social disapproval by dissociation from the criminal who demonstrates disagreement with the likeliness to act against the
basic law of proper human coexistence (p. 64). Essentially, punishment has historically meant losing the ability to freely
associate with other men, so Lee suggests a police-supervised penal colony where criminals could trade among themselves and
with outsiders (without leaving, however), while bearing the supervisory, administrative and restitutive costs of their crime
(pp. 64-5). Lee thus limits “punishment” to the enforced dissociation of the society from the criminal.
Desert
of punishment rests upon a person’s demonstrating “that he is not willing to search out reasonable agreement with
his fellow men and thus not to be trusted in the free association with his fellowmen…,” that he “acted
in such a way as to undermine” the type of social interaction which is conducive to long-range well-being, and that
he thus “ought to be excluded from free association with those members of the free advanced society who have not so
acted” (p. 65).
But even though Lee’s proposal is far more reasonable than many voiced by others (even Libertarians), I still
have qualms about going even that far. Referring back to my remarks in REB #2, I again raise the question
as to whether a proof is available showing that “it is morally obligatory for us to set up a system which allows a small
number of men [or even a large number!] to decide whether or not all men must agree to the forcible exclusion
of the criminal from society, i.e., whether we ought to delegate our right of ostracism [the right to voluntarily
deal with someone, which is merely a corollary of the right to free association] to our protective agency or government.”
Why is it in every man’s rational self-interest
to make society-wide ostracism an enforceable Rule of the Game, as it were, if self-defense is not involved? (And
if self-defense is involved, why call it “punishment”?? There are other problems in justifying
such blanket ostracism, such as proving the intent of the criminal to continue violating rights, but this seems to me the
crucial question.
[1] The material following the opening paragraph is the editorial from issue #2 (April
1974) of my “Independent Libertarian Newsletter,” REB.
[2] This is substantially the same paper that I delivered under the title “Punishment—an
Unnecessary Evil?” to the Holland Conference on Saturday, March 30, 1974. Professor Hospers’ own paper, “Justice
and Punishment,” and his reply to mine failed to convince me that I needed to make any major revision, either in my
own position, or in my critique of his. I included it in issue #2 (April 1974) of REB, so that those who weren’t
able to attend the Conference would be able to participate in the dialogue and perhaps suggest some modifications before I
submitted my Open Letter to the Libertarian Party Platform Committee (or maybe reasons why I shouldn’t—e.g., a
valid argument in favor of punishment) in May of 1974. I received no further input from REB subscribers and no response
to the LP Platform Committee.
[iii] This essay was published in issue #3 (August 1974) of REB.
[iv] This essay was published in issue #3 (August 1974) of REB.